People with a form
of Body Dysmorphia called Body Integrity Identity Disorder (BIID) who
have voluntary amputations cause a dissonance with our concept of
normal which we, the observers of those with BIID, use to determine
what is or is not good. This results in either labeling of the
condition as a mental illness or a questioning of our concept of
normal. I believe that voluntary amputees deserve the second option.
To demonstrate this, I am placing those who want to voluntarily
amputate themselves in the gray area between transsexuals who
justifiably go through Sex Reassignment Surgery (SRS) and anorexics
who wrongfully damage their bodies. From there, I wish to argue that
an understanding of the kind of body dysmorphia voluntary amputees
have is like that of transsexuals rather than like that of anorexics.
This would give the basis of suggesting that this form of body
dysmorphia's solution belongs to the category 'normal' where normal
is to be understood as healthy, morally permissible, and not
irrational. I will end by addressing some objections to the
amputation procedure on healthy limbs for voluntary amputees.
I
There are two
conditions related to Body Integrity Identity Disorder. One is Body
Dysmorphic Disorder (BDD), which Tim Bayne and Neil Levy describe
well in their article Amputees By Choice: Body Integrity Identity
Disorder and the Ethics of Amputation. They define BDD as the
following:
Body Dysmorphic Disorder is a condition in which the individual
believes, incorrectly, that a part of their body is diseased or
exceedingly ugly. This belief can be a matter of intense concern for
the individual, and is resistant to evidence against it. BDD appears
closely akin to anorexia nervosa, in hat both appear to be
monothematic delusions that sustained by misperceptions of one's
body. (Baynes 75-76)
The other is Gender Identity Disorder (GID) which transsexuals have.
The A.D.A.M. Medical Encyclopedia defines GID as:
Gender identity disorder is a conflict between
a person's actual physical gender and the gender that person
identifies himself or herself as. For example, a person identified as
a boy may actually feel and act like a girl. The person experiences
significant discomfort with the biological sex they were born.
(A.D.A.M.)
Both conditions can lead to current-body-averse behavior. For
instance, young male transsexuals are known to self-amputate their
external genitalia as a way of handling the discomfort of feeling
like they are in the wrong body in regards to biological sex.
Voluntary Amputees with BIID feel that internal body image does not
fit their actual body. This is different significantly different from
BDD because people with BIID do not have the delusion that the
undesired body part is diseased or ugly. BIID is a feeling of
mismatched mind-body identity that strikingly similar to that of GID.
Mismatched body
identity is not uncommon1
because the reverse of the BIID occurs with amputees often. This
reversal of the condition is phantom limbs for which a person's
mental image of his or her body contains a limb that they no longer
have. The feeling of phantom limbs is so strong that phantom pains
occur in the mind despite the nerve endings no longer being there. In
the case of people with BIID, the feeling is that the healthy limb is
not really part of their body. This feeling is the cementing
factor that when understood as being in this relation to GID and
phantom limbs, voluntary amputation become normal for people with
BIID.
II
Normal, as I said
earlier, is the concept of being healthy, morally permissible, and
not irrational. Normal is often devalued as being a social construct
that has caused great harm to the 'different'. Unlike those who hold
this understanding of normal, I will defend it as being central to
our species project towards a better understanding of health, other
minds, and the world in general.
In regards to
health, normal acts as a inductive conclusion that certain qualities
indicate illness. The qualia valances associated with beauty and
ugliness are so ingrained with our species that most humans are born
with the same instinctive perception of beauty and ugliness. This
helps explain why health is often associated with beauty and illness
is often associated with ugliness. The grossness of sickness acts as
a deterrent in our species away from things which may cause us to
become ill ourselves and to take recognition of something being
'wrong' in the other we perceive.
In the case of
voluntary amputees, our misunderstanding-based response is to think
that the person has a self-destructive mental sickness. As with the
evolution with our views on transsexuality, I believe that given the
similarities, our investigation into BIID will lead to a general
understanding of the normalcy of the condition. The issue concerning
whether or not amputation is harm will be addressed in the next
section.
The second aspect
of normal is that it is morally permissible. Society, in part, makes
the abnormal by both de facto and de jure attitudes towards acts,
beliefs, conditions, etc. In one society, being homosexual is taboo
so homosexuality appears to those in the society generally as
abnormal. In another, homosexuality included into the mainstream and
the fact there are homosexuals is part of the normal for those in
that society.
Of course, societal
consensus is not enough to establish what is actually morally
permissible, but societies invested in morality ought to invest in
understanding the world in which we actually live in. This is because
generally taboos about things like homosexuality come with genuine
beliefs about the nature of homosexuality and what kind of entities
exist in this world that act as moral law-givers. If those beliefs
are not true, this can and often does lead to harming people despite
the good intentions of the law or taboo.
This relates to
BIID in that the desire to be amputated was believed to be a
psycho-sexual condition (Bayne 76). It was believed by psychologists
that this desire to be an amputated was the desire to be the
receivers of apotemnophilia, or the sexual attraction for amputees
(Bayne 76). The taboos against deviant sexual desires and acts
underlies the labeling this desire negatively, or as abnormal.
Abnormal is often
associated with irrationality. For instance, if I wanted to eat it
would be irrational or abnormal for me to refuse food to which I am
not averse. I say normal is being not irrational because normal can
be either rational or nonrational. It would be rational for me to eat
when I am hungry, but my tastes and my desire to eat are nonrational.
The foundational desires that I have no grounds on which to be in
themselves rational. There is no reason to live but through of the
desires to live or the desires which are satisfied through living.
This is why euthanasia is morally permissible when all the conditions
that make life of the one to be euthanized desirable are gone for
both the person suffering and the invested party like dependents.
This understood allows for making an extremely important distinction
between illness-driven behavior like that of anorexics and
justifiable behavior like that of transsexuals receiving SRS.
This understanding
leads to that distinction because mental illness leads to undesirable
outcomes like death. Neither the anorexic nor his or her relatives
want the anorexic to die. The desire to lose weight that the anorexic
has is conditioned by a false representation of reality, particularly
that they are overweight. The desire would cease when their beliefs
change to more healthily reflect reality. The transsexual and the
voluntary amputee, all things equal, have correct beliefs about their
bodies but the desire stems from their very understanding of self,
which is not conditioned by false beliefs about the physical body
they have.2
The truism that captures the general idea here is 'who I am is not
what I am'.3
III
In this section, I
will address three objections to voluntary amputation of healthy
limbs that challenge the moral status of the very idea of voluntary
amputation, BIID aside. If successful, these objections override the
desire satisfaction that voluntary amputation achieves, all things
equal, desires being a good enough reason to do something.
- When we contemplate whether or not being amputate someone, we always desire not to amputate because amputation should only be done as a necessary evil to save someone's life. Losing a limb, in other words, is a serious harm, and even if a person wants to lose a limb, it is wrong to seriously harm someone even if they want us to.
The understanding
that amputation is necessarily harmful is such a strong intuition
that it characterizes our medical practice, which avoids amputation
unless risk is high enough to the person's life, as this objection
alludes. If amputation was a serious harm necessarily, then even a
person with BIID would not justifiably be able to get a voluntary
amputation. This intuition that amputation is necessarily harmful is
false.
Harm must be put
into context with human experience and threat to self because we are
after all trying to have a moral landscape that reflects the world we
live in. Those without experience of BIID would induce from their
limited understanding of human desires that it is universally
undesirable to be an amputee. This is an easy move because there are
so few with BIID, so an ethicist can feel comfortable with the
informal sampling of human population she has in her life of moral
science.
A thought
experiment might help here. It is a common assumption that the
default is not to amputate, but this would be assuming that a neutral
body would be harmed by amputation. A doctor is deciding on a
procedure to take on a patient. This patient is, however, completely
neutral, meaning he has neither any aversions nor any attractions.
The doctor could cut of the patients arm, and the patient would not
care. Nothing the doctor can change the patient's true condition
which is neutrality. If the doctor were to cure this neutrality,
perhaps by reading him Albert Camus's Myth of Sisyphus, the
doctor cannot assume that the patient will necessarily not have right
arm aversion.
In other words, it
is not because amputation is universally harmful, but only in the
experience of the majority who do not have BIID is it wrong to
amputate because they do not desire as a block to live a life as
amputees. Because harm must be understood in terms of how people
experience world, being an experience itself, and because amputation
is not universally a harmful experience, amputation cannot be as a
rule be necessarily harmful, despite that being usually the case.4
- Humans seek to reach certain ends like living independently. Amputations decrease the utility of the body which a person uses to achieve ends. A person who voluntarily amputates when confronted with something they could have only done with the limb he had amputated will feel regret. Since the loss of utility is great when one is amputated, voluntary amputation of healthy limbs cannot be justified.
This regret is a
serious problem which is the purpose psychological exams of those
with BIID and GID have before their life-changing surgeries. Like
male-to-female-to-male transsexuals, there is the risk that someone
who voluntarily amputates will find him- or herself desiring to
reverse the procedure. Despite this serious risk, the risk is
justifiable.
Every time a human
makes a decision, some utility is expended, and regret over what
could have been is made possible. This is the human condition to
always be under the threat of regret. The psychological exams before
the voluntary amputation are necessary to reduce this risk to a
reasonable level.
- The good life is a project of growth. We extend our lives, strengthen our bodies, and rid ourselves from disease. Just like it is irrational to not to be death-averse, it is irrational to weaken the body when the virtuous goal is to be a greater being. In other words, the virtuous person ought to overcome the desire to amputate in order to continue on the path of self-betterment.
I am most
sympathetic to this objection. Though the utility argument could have
been construed this way, this transhumanist argument hits the nail on
the head. The best counter I can provide is that better can be
achieved without ones limbs. It takes a certain creativity to imagine
what it is like to be without ones limbs. Just like those who are
blind whose hearing becomes stronger to compensate, without limbs a
new strength can be sought.
Anyways, this new
strength has been sought ever since people started dedicating
themselves to academics. The body became a tool to carry the head to
classes. We have constantly replaced the body with intellectual
pursuits which in many ways made us more powerful than our bodies
could have ever been. Since the body is merely a tool to achieve
these goals of virtues, new better tools can replace the body's
traditional purpose, making the body only important in-so-far as
having a long, comfortable, mentally aware life is concerned. The
car is faster than any person who has ever lived; the computer is
faster than any brain that ever existed. Those with amputations can
live virtuous lives in this day and age precisely because the body
with which people are born is becoming less and less essential to
achieving virtue.
While this does not
cover all the objections, this outlines how something seemingly
abnormal like voluntary amputations may in fact be normal after
investigation. Any objection to the risk of amputations will have to
refer to the way the world is because risk is not an a priori
concept. Any declaration of wrongness must avoid merely projecting
ones own feelings onto people who do not have them. Even if BIID ends
up being an illness rather that should be cured by treatment of the
mind rather than treatment of the body, amputees can live fulfilling
lives more and more, making the moral consequences of amputating
someone who should not have been amputated less and less.
Works Cited:
Bayne, Tim. Levy, Neil. “Amputees By Choice: Body Integrity
Identity Disorder and the Ethics of Amputation.” Journal of
Applied Philosophy. Vol. 1, No. 1, 2005. Society of Applied
Philosophy. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford: 2005.
A.D.A.M. Gender Identity Disorder. U.S. National Library of
Medicine. ncbi.nlm.nih.gov.
A.D.A.M., Inc. 2012. Date Accesses: April 18, 2012.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmedhealth/PMH0002495/
>
1Being
common is closely associated with our concept of 'normal', which I
will flesh out in the next section.
2This
is only part of the story of distinguish the irrational from the not
irrational. There are distinctions like that for fear-desires. What
makes a fear-desire irrational (phobias) rather than nonrational
might require more nuance than the story of rationality that I am
providing here because fear-desires can run very deep yet retain a
semblance of irrationality.
3I
only sort of believe this. I would say that you are still a what but
you can change what you are and remain you because identity is a set
of whats and these whats do not necessarily essentialize everything
about ones body. I avoid the debate around identity here and simply
go with something I merely admit as a truism.
4It
might be helpful here that I am not saying just any perception of
the world overrules whether or not something is harmful. For
instance, a person might perceive, incorrectly, that water is
harmful. With the understanding that the person's fear stems from
instincts that tends towards survival, it would doing the person a
favor to help them over their life-threatening fear. Again, I am
going to avoid addressing phobias directly in the body of this paper
because of the problems they provide for the story of desire-based
ethics I am pushing here.
It seems that "healthy, morally permissible, and not irrational" are only certain aspects of being normal. Just wondering; is avoiding other aspects of what the word normal connotes a good way to go? Isn't it too convenient to say normal doesn't mean common when you don't want it to mean common? I agree that voluntary amputation is not morally wrong and it should be not considered a disorder. However, I'm not persuaded yet to think it's normal.
ReplyDelete